友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!阅读过程发现任何错误请告诉我们,谢谢!! 报告错误
哔哔读书 返回本书目录 我的书架 我的书签 TXT全本下载 进入书吧 加入书签

prior analytics-第35章

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!






latter proves the major term to belong to the third term by means of



the middle; the former proves the major to belong to the middle by



means of the third。 In the order of nature; syllogism through the



middle term is prior and better known; but syllogism through induction



is clearer to us。







                                24







  We have an 'example' when the major term is proved to belong to



the middle by means of a term which resembles the third。 It ought to



be known both that the middle belongs to the third term; and that



the first belongs to that which resembles the third。 For example let A



be evil; B making war against neighbours; C Athenians against Thebans;



D Thebans against Phocians。 If then we wish to prove that to fight



with the Thebans is an evil; we must assume that to fight against



neighbours is an evil。 Evidence of this is obtained from similar



cases; e。g。 that the war against the Phocians was an evil to the



Thebans。 Since then to fight against neighbours is an evil; and to



fight against the Thebans is to fight against neighbours; it is



clear that to fight against the Thebans is an evil。 Now it is clear



that B belongs to C and to D (for both are cases of making war upon



one's neighbours) and that A belongs to D (for the war against the



Phocians did not turn out well for the Thebans): but that A belongs to



B will be proved through D。 Similarly if the belief in the relation of



the middle term to the extreme should be produced by several similar



cases。 Clearly then to argue by example is neither like reasoning from



part to whole; nor like reasoning from whole to part; but rather



reasoning from part to part; when both particulars are subordinate



to the same term; and one of them is known。 It differs from induction;



because induction starting from all the particular cases proves (as we



saw) that the major term belongs to the middle; and does not apply the



syllogistic conclusion to the minor term; whereas argument by



example does make this application and does not draw its proof from



all the particular cases。







                                25







  By reduction we mean an argument in which the first term clearly



belongs to the middle; but the relation of the middle to the last term



is uncertain though equally or more probable than the conclusion; or



again an argument in which the terms intermediate between the last



term and the middle are few。 For in any of these cases it turns out



that we approach more nearly to knowledge。 For example let A stand for



what can be taught; B for knowledge; C for justice。 Now it is clear



that knowledge can be taught: but it is uncertain whether virtue is



knowledge。 If now the statement BC is equally or more probable than



AC; we have a reduction: for we are nearer to knowledge; since we have



taken a new term; being so far without knowledge that A belongs to



C。 Or again suppose that the terms intermediate between B and C are



few: for thus too we are nearer knowledge。 For example let D stand for



squaring; E for rectilinear figure; F for circle。 If there were only



one term intermediate between E and F (viz。 that the circle is made



equal to a rectilinear figure by the help of lunules); we should be



near to knowledge。 But when BC is not more probable than AC; and the



intermediate terms are not few; I do not call this reduction: nor



again when the statement BC is immediate: for such a statement is



knowledge。







                                26







  An objection is a premiss contrary to a premiss。 It differs from a



premiss; because it may be particular; but a premiss either cannot



be particular at all or not in universal syllogisms。 An objection is



brought in two ways and through two figures; in two ways because every



objection is either universal or particular; by two figures because



objections are brought in opposition to the premiss; and opposites can



be proved only in the first and third figures。 If a man maintains a



universal affirmative; we reply with a universal or a particular



negative; the former is proved from the first figure; the latter



from the third。 For example let stand for there being a single



science; B for contraries。 If a man premises that contraries are



subjects of a single science; the objection may be either that



opposites are never subjects of a single science; and contraries are



opposites; so that we get the first figure; or that the knowable and



the unknowable are not subjects of a single science: this proof is



in the third figure: for it is true of C (the knowable and the



unknowable) that they are contraries; and it is false that they are



the subjects of a single science。



  Similarly if the premiss objected to is negative。 For if a man



maintains that contraries are not subjects of a single science; we



reply either that all opposites or that certain contraries; e。g。



what is healthy and what is sickly; are subjects of the same



science: the former argument issues from the first; the latter from



the third figure。



  In general if a man urges a universal objection he must frame his



contradiction with reference to the universal of the terms taken by



his opponent; e。g。 if a man maintains that contraries are not subjects



of the same science; his opponent must reply that there is a single



science of all opposites。 Thus we must have the first figure: for



the term which embraces the original subject becomes the middle term。



  If the objection is particular; the objector must frame his



contradiction with reference to a term relatively to which the subject



of his opponent's premiss is universal; e。g。 he will point out that



the knowable and the unknowable are not subjects of the same



science: 'contraries' is universal relatively to these。 And we have



the third figure: for the particular term assumed is middle; e。g。



the knowable and the unknowable。 Premisses from which it is possible



to draw the contrary conclusion are what we start from when we try



to make objections。 Consequently we bring objections in these



figures only: for in them only are opposite syllogisms possible; since



the second figure cannot produce an affirmative conclusion。



  Besides; an objection in the middle figure would require a fuller



argument; e。g。 if it should not be granted that A belongs to B;



because C does not follow B。 This can be made clear only by other



premisses。 But an objection ought not to turn off into other things;



but have its new premiss quite clear immediately。 For this reason also



this is the only figure from which proof by signs cannot be obtained。



  We must consider later the other kinds of objection; namely the



objection from contraries; from similars; and from common opinion; and



inquire whether a particular objection cannot be elicited from the



first figure or a negative objection from the second。







                                27







  A probability and a sign are not identical; but a probability is a



generally approved proposition: what men know to happen or not to



happen; to be or not to be; for the most part thus and thus; is a



probability; e。g。 'the envious hate'; 'the beloved show affection'。



A sign means a demonstrative proposition necessary or generally



approved: for anything such that when it is another thing is; or



when it has come into being the other has come into being before or



after; is a sign of the other's being or having come into being。 Now



an enthymeme is a syllogism starting from probabilities or signs;



and a sign may be taken in thre
返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0
未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!