友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!阅读过程发现任何错误请告诉我们,谢谢!! 报告错误
哔哔读书 返回本书目录 我的书架 我的书签 TXT全本下载 进入书吧 加入书签

prior analytics-第34章

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!






actual exercise; nor on the other hand has his thought caused an error



contrary to his knowledge: for the error contrary to the knowledge



of the universal would be a syllogism。



  But he who thinks the essence of good is the essence of bad will



think the same thing to be the essence of good and the essence of bad。



Let A stand for the essence of good and B for the essence of bad;



and again C for the essence of good。 Since then he thinks B and C



identical; he will think that C is B; and similarly that B is A;



consequently that C is A。 For just as we saw that if B is true of



all of which C is true; and A is true of all of which B is true; A



is true of C; similarly with the word 'think'。 Similarly also with the



word 'is'; for we saw that if C is the same as B; and B as A; C is the



same as A。 Similarly therefore with 'opine'。 Perhaps then this is



necessary if a man will grant the first point。 But presumably that



is false; that any one could suppose the essence of good to be the



essence of bad; save incidentally。 For it is possible to think this in



many different ways。 But we must consider this matter better。







                                22







  Whenever the extremes are convertible it is necessary that the



middle should be convertible with both。 For if A belongs to C



through B; then if A and C are convertible and C belongs everything to



which A belongs; B is convertible with A; and B belongs to



everything to which A belongs; through C as middle; and C is



convertible with B through A as middle。 Similarly if the conclusion is



negative; e。g。 if B belongs to C; but A does not belong to B;



neither will A belong to C。 If then B is convertible with A; C will be



convertible with A。 Suppose B does not belong to A; neither then



will C: for ex hypothesi B belonged to all C。 And if C is



convertible with B; B is convertible also with A; for C is said of



that of all of which B is said。 And if C is convertible in relation to



A and to B; B also is convertible in relation to A。 For C belongs to



that to which B belongs: but C does not belong to that to which A



belongs。 And this alone starts from the conclusion; the preceding



moods do not do so as in the affirmative syllogism。 Again if A and B



are convertible; and similarly C and D; and if A or C must belong to



anything whatever; then B and D will be such that one or other belongs



to anything whatever。 For since B belongs to that to which A



belongs; and D belongs to that to which C belongs; and since A or C



belongs to everything; but not together; it is clear that B or D



belongs to everything; but not together。 For example if that which



is uncreated is incorruptible and that which is incorruptible is



uncreated; it is necessary that what is created should be



corruptible and what is corruptible should have been created。 For



two syllogisms have been put together。 Again if A or B belongs to



everything and if C or D belongs to everything; but they cannot belong



together; then when A and C are convertible B and D are convertible。



For if B does not belong to something to which D belongs; it is



clear that A belongs to it。 But if A then C: for they are convertible。



Therefore C and D belong together。 But this is impossible。 When A



belongs to the whole of B and to C and is affirmed of nothing else;



and B also belongs to all C; it is necessary that A and B should be



convertible: for since A is said of B and C only; and B is affirmed



both of itself and of C; it is clear that B will be said of everything



of which A is said; except A itself。 Again when A and B belong to



the whole of C; and C is convertible with B; it is necessary that A



should belong to all B: for since A belongs to all C; and C to B by



conversion; A will belong to all B。



  When; of two opposites A and B; A is preferable to B; and



similarly D is preferable to C; then if A and C together are



preferable to B and D together; A must be preferable to D。 For A is an



object of desire to the same extent as B is an object of aversion;



since they are opposites: and C is similarly related to D; since



they also are opposites。 If then A is an object of desire to the



same extent as D; B is an object of aversion to the same extent as C



(since each is to the same extent as each…the one an object of



aversion; the other an object of desire)。 Therefore both A and C



together; and B and D together; will be equally objects of desire or



aversion。 But since A and C are preferable to B and D; A cannot be



equally desirable with D; for then B along with D would be equally



desirable with A along with C。 But if D is preferable to A; then B



must be less an object of aversion than C: for the less is opposed



to the less。 But the greater good and lesser evil are preferable to



the lesser good and greater evil: the whole BD then is preferable to



the whole AC。 But ex hypothesi this is not so。 A then is preferable to



D; and C consequently is less an object of aversion than B。 If then



every lover in virtue of his love would prefer A; viz。 that the



beloved should be such as to grant a favour; and yet should not



grant it (for which C stands); to the beloved's granting the favour



(represented by D) without being such as to grant it (represented by



B); it is clear that A (being of such a nature) is preferable to



granting the favour。 To receive affection then is preferable in love



to sexual intercourse。 Love then is more dependent on friendship



than on intercourse。 And if it is most dependent on receiving



affection; then this is its end。 Intercourse then either is not an end



at all or is an end relative to the further end; the receiving of



affection。 And indeed the same is true of the other desires and arts。







                                23







  It is clear then how the terms are related in conversion; and in



respect of being in a higher degree objects of aversion or of



desire。 We must now state that not only dialectical and



demonstrative syllogisms are formed by means of the aforesaid figures;



but also rhetorical syllogisms and in general any form of



persuasion; however it may be presented。 For every belief comes either



through syllogism or from induction。



  Now induction; or rather the syllogism which springs out of



induction; consists in establishing syllogistically a relation between



one extreme and the middle by means of the other extreme; e。g。 if B is



the middle term between A and C; it consists in proving through C that



A belongs to B。 For this is the manner in which we make inductions。



For example let A stand for long…lived; B for bileless; and C for



the particular long…lived animals; e。g。 man; horse; mule。 A then



belongs to the whole of C: for whatever is bileless is long…lived。 But



B also ('not possessing bile') belongs to all C。 If then C is



convertible with B; and the middle term is not wider in extension;



it is necessary that A should belong to B。 For it has already been



proved that if two things belong to the same thing; and the extreme is



convertible with one of them; then the other predicate will belong



to the predicate that is converted。 But we must apprehend C as made up



of all the particulars。 For induction proceeds through an



enumeration of all the cases。



  Such is the syllogism which establishes the first and immediate



premiss: for where there is a middle term the syllogism proceeds



through the middle term; when there is no middle term; through



induction。 And in a way induction is opposed to syllogism: for the



latter proves the major term to belong to the thir
返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0
未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!