友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!阅读过程发现任何错误请告诉我们,谢谢!! 报告错误
哔哔读书 返回本书目录 我的书架 我的书签 TXT全本下载 进入书吧 加入书签

prior analytics-第28章

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!






converted into its contrary。 For if A does not belong to some C; but



to all B; then B will not belong to some C。 But the original premiss



is not yet refuted: for it is possible that B should belong to some C;



and should not belong to some C。 The universal premiss AB cannot be



affected by a syllogism at all: for if A does not belong to some of



the Cs; but B belongs to some of the Cs; neither of the premisses is



universal。 Similarly if the syllogism is negative: for if it should be



assumed that A belongs to all C; both premisses are refuted: but if



the assumption is that A belongs to some C; neither premiss is



refuted。 The proof is the same as before。







                                 9







  In the second figure it is not possible to refute the premiss



which concerns the major extreme by establishing something contrary to



it; whichever form the conversion of the conclusion may take。 For



the conclusion of the refutation will always be in the third figure;



and in this figure (as we saw) there is no universal syllogism。 The



other premiss can be refuted in a manner similar to the conversion:



I mean; if the conclusion of the first syllogism is converted into its



contrary; the conclusion of the refutation will be the contrary of the



minor premiss of the first; if into its contradictory; the



contradictory。 Let A belong to all B and to no C: conclusion BC。 If



then it is assumed that B belongs to all C; and the proposition AB



stands; A will belong to all C; since the first figure is produced。 If



B belongs to all C; and A to no C; then A belongs not to all B: the



figure is the last。 But if the conclusion BC is converted into its



contradictory; the premiss AB will be refuted as before; the



premiss; AC by its contradictory。 For if B belongs to some C; and A to



no C; then A will not belong to some B。 Again if B belongs to some



C; and A to all B; A will belong to some C; so that the syllogism



results in the contradictory of the minor premiss。 A similar proof can



be given if the premisses are transposed in respect of their quality。



  If the syllogism is particular; when the conclusion is converted



into its contrary neither premiss can be refuted; as also happened



in the first figure;' if the conclusion is converted into its



contradictory; both premisses can be refuted。 Suppose that A belongs



to no B; and to some C: the conclusion is BC。 If then it is assumed



that B belongs to some C; and the statement AB stands; the



conclusion will be that A does not belong to some C。 But the



original statement has not been refuted: for it is possible that A



should belong to some C and also not to some C。 Again if B belongs



to some C and A to some C; no syllogism will be possible: for



neither of the premisses taken is universal。 Consequently the



proposition AB is not refuted。 But if the conclusion is converted into



its contradictory; both premisses can be refuted。 For if B belongs



to all C; and A to no B; A will belong to no C: but it was assumed



to belong to some C。 Again if B belongs to all C and A to some C; A



will belong to some B。 The same proof can be given if the universal



statement is affirmative。







                                10







  In the third figure when the conclusion is converted into its



contrary; neither of the premisses can be refuted in any of the



syllogisms; but when the conclusion is converted into its



contradictory; both premisses may be refuted and in all the moods。



Suppose it has been proved that A belongs to some B; C being taken



as middle; and the premisses being universal。 If then it is assumed



that A does not belong to some B; but B belongs to all C; no syllogism



is formed about A and C。 Nor if A does not belong to some B; but



belongs to all C; will a syllogism be possible about B and C。 A



similar proof can be given if the premisses are not universal。 For



either both premisses arrived at by the conversion must be particular;



or the universal premiss must refer to the minor extreme。 But we found



that no syllogism is possible thus either in the first or in the



middle figure。 But if the conclusion is converted into its



contradictory; both the premisses can be refuted。 For if A belongs



to no B; and B to all C; then A belongs to no C: again if A belongs to



no B; and to all C; B belongs to no C。 And similarly if one of the



premisses is not universal。 For if A belongs to no B; and B to some C;



A will not belong to some C: if A belongs to no B; and to C; B will



belong to no C。



  Similarly if the original syllogism is negative。 Suppose it has been



proved that A does not belong to some B; BC being affirmative; AC



being negative: for it was thus that; as we saw; a syllogism could



be made。 Whenever then the contrary of the conclusion is assumed a



syllogism will not be possible。 For if A belongs to some B; and B to



all C; no syllogism is possible (as we saw) about A and C。 Nor; if A



belongs to some B; and to no C; was a syllogism possible concerning



B and C。 Therefore the premisses are not refuted。 But when the



contradictory of the conclusion is assumed; they are refuted。 For if A



belongs to all B; and B to C; A belongs to all C: but A was supposed



originally to belong to no C。 Again if A belongs to all B; and to no



C; then B belongs to no C: but it was supposed to belong to all C。 A



similar proof is possible if the premisses are not universal。 For AC



becomes universal and negative; the other premiss particular and



affirmative。 If then A belongs to all B; and B to some C; it results



that A belongs to some C: but it was supposed to belong to no C。 Again



if A belongs to all B; and to no C; then B belongs to no C: but it was



assumed to belong to some C。 If A belongs to some B and B to some C;



no syllogism results: nor yet if A belongs to some B; and to no C。



Thus in one way the premisses are refuted; in the other way they are



not。



  From what has been said it is clear how a syllogism results in



each figure when the conclusion is converted; when a result contrary



to the premiss; and when a result contradictory to the premiss; is



obtained。 It is clear that in the first figure the syllogisms are



formed through the middle and the last figures; and the premiss



which concerns the minor extreme is alway refuted through the middle



figure; the premiss which concerns the major through the last



figure。 In the second figure syllogisms proceed through the first



and the last figures; and the premiss which concerns the minor extreme



is always refuted through the first figure; the premiss which concerns



the major extreme through the last。 In the third figure the refutation



proceeds through the first and the middle figures; the premiss which



concerns the major is always refuted through the first figure; the



premiss which concerns the minor through the middle figure。



                                11







  It is clear then what conversion is; how it is effected in each



figure; and what syllogism results。 The syllogism per impossibile is



proved when the contradictory of the conclusion stated and another



premiss is assumed; it can be made in all the figures。 For it



resembles conversion; differing only in this: conversion takes place



after a syllogism has been formed and both the premisses have been



taken; but a reduction to the impossible takes place not because the



contradictory has been agreed to already; but because it is clear that



it is true。 The terms are alike in both; and the premisses of both are



taken in the same way。 For example if A belongs to 
返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0
未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!