友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!阅读过程发现任何错误请告诉我们,谢谢!! 报告错误
哔哔读书 返回本书目录 我的书架 我的书签 TXT全本下载 进入书吧 加入书签

prior analytics-第13章

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!






third。 But when the minor premiss is negative and universal; if it



is problematic a syllogism can be formed by means of conversion; but



if it is necessary a syllogism is not possible。 The proof will



follow the same course as where the premisses are universal; and the



same terms may be used。



  It is clear then in this figure also when and how a syllogism can be



formed; and when the conclusion is problematic; and when it is pure。



It is evident also that all syllogisms in this figure are imperfect;



and that they are made perfect by means of the first figure。







                                23







  It is clear from what has been said that the syllogisms in these



figures are made perfect by means of universal syllogisms in the first



figure and are reduced to them。 That every syllogism without



qualification can be so treated; will be clear presently; when it



has been proved that every syllogism is formed through one or other of



these figures。



  It is necessary that every demonstration and every syllogism



should prove either that something belongs or that it does not; and



this either universally or in part; and further either ostensively



or hypothetically。 One sort of hypothetical proof is the reductio ad



impossibile。 Let us speak first of ostensive syllogisms: for after



these have been pointed out the truth of our contention will be



clear with regard to those which are proved per impossibile; and in



general hypothetically。



  If then one wants to prove syllogistically A of B; either as an



attribute of it or as not an attribute of it; one must assert



something of something else。 If now A should be asserted of B; the



proposition originally in question will have been assumed。 But if A



should be asserted of C; but C should not be asserted of anything; nor



anything of it; nor anything else of A; no syllogism will be possible。



For nothing necessarily follows from the assertion of some one thing



concerning some other single thing。 Thus we must take another



premiss as well。 If then A be asserted of something else; or something



else of A; or something different of C; nothing prevents a syllogism



being formed; but it will not be in relation to B through the



premisses taken。 Nor when C belongs to something else; and that to



something else and so on; no connexion however being made with B; will



a syllogism be possible concerning A in its relation to B。 For in



general we stated that no syllogism can establish the attribution of



one thing to another; unless some middle term is taken; which is



somehow related to each by way of predication。 For the syllogism in



general is made out of premisses; and a syllogism referring to this



out of premisses with the same reference; and a syllogism relating



this to that proceeds through premisses which relate this to that。 But



it is impossible to take a premiss in reference to B; if we neither



affirm nor deny anything of it; or again to take a premiss relating



A to B; if we take nothing common; but affirm or deny peculiar



attributes of each。 So we must take something midway between the



two; which will connect the predications; if we are to have a



syllogism relating this to that。 If then we must take something common



in relation to both; and this is possible in three ways (either by



predicating A of C; and C of B; or C of both; or both of C); and these



are the figures of which we have spoken; it is clear that every



syllogism must be made in one or other of these figures。 The



argument is the same if several middle terms should be necessary to



establish the relation to B; for the figure will be the same whether



there is one middle term or many。



  It is clear then that the ostensive syllogisms are effected by means



of the aforesaid figures; these considerations will show that



reductiones ad also are effected in the same way。 For all who effect



an argument per impossibile infer syllogistically what is false; and



prove the original conclusion hypothetically when something impossible



results from the assumption of its contradictory; e。g。 that the



diagonal of the square is incommensurate with the side; because odd



numbers are equal to evens if it is supposed to be commensurate。 One



infers syllogistically that odd numbers come out equal to evens; and



one proves hypothetically the incommensurability of the diagonal;



since a falsehood results through contradicting this。 For this we



found to be reasoning per impossibile; viz。 proving something



impossible by means of an hypothesis conceded at the beginning。



Consequently; since the falsehood is established in reductions ad



impossibile by an ostensive syllogism; and the original conclusion



is proved hypothetically; and we have already stated that ostensive



syllogisms are effected by means of these figures; it is evident



that syllogisms per impossibile also will be made through these



figures。 Likewise all the other hypothetical syllogisms: for in



every case the syllogism leads up to the proposition that is



substituted for the original thesis; but the original thesis is



reached by means of a concession or some other hypothesis。 But if this



is true; every demonstration and every syllogism must be formed by



means of the three figures mentioned above。 But when this has been



shown it is clear that every syllogism is perfected by means of the



first figure and is reducible to the universal syllogisms in this



figure。



                                24







  Further in every syllogism one of the premisses must be affirmative;



and universality must be present: unless one of the premisses is



universal either a syllogism will not be possible; or it will not



refer to the subject proposed; or the original position will be



begged。 Suppose we have to prove that pleasure in music is good。 If



one should claim as a premiss that pleasure is good without adding



'all'; no syllogism will be possible; if one should claim that some



pleasure is good; then if it is different from pleasure in music; it



is not relevant to the subject proposed; if it is this very



pleasure; one is assuming that which was proposed at the outset to



be proved。 This is more obvious in geometrical proofs; e。g。 that the



angles at the base of an isosceles triangle are equal。 Suppose the



lines A and B have been drawn to the centre。 If then one should assume



that the angle AC is equal to the angle BD; without claiming generally



that angles of semicircles are equal; and again if one should assume



that the angle C is equal to the angle D; without the additional



assumption that every angle of a segment is equal to every other angle



of the same segment; and further if one should assume that when



equal angles are taken from the whole angles; which are themselves



equal; the remainders E and F are equal; he will beg the thing to be



proved; unless he also states that when equals are taken from equals



the remainders are equal。



  It is clear then that in every syllogism there must be a universal



premiss; and that a universal statement is proved only when all the



premisses are universal; while a particular statement is proved both



from two universal premisses and from one only: consequently if the



conclusion is universal; the premisses also must be universal; but



if the premisses are universal it is possible that the conclusion



may not be universal。 And it is clear also that in every syllogism



either both or one of the premisses must be like the conclusion。 I



mean not only in being affirmative or negative; but also in being



necessary;
返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0
未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!